This week’s Upstream episode is a discussion with David Sacks about his intellectual and political journey to where he is today.
This week’s Moment of Zen episode is about picking markets, NFTs, disinformation, fentanyl, and more.
This week’s Cognitive Revolution features Nathan Labenz on AI causing economic transformation and Jaan Tallinn on why he wrote the AI pause letter.
This is the first post in a series on liberalism
Liberalism introduced a radically new notion of freedom: freedom for the individual, from society itself — including all inherited culture, religion, custom, tradition, hierarchy, place, behavioral norms, associations, and relationships standing in the way of the fulfillment of individual desires.
This was a radical departure from the old definition of freedom. The newer view, echoing Locke, to view liberty as the ability of the individual to exercise choice in the pursuit of the satisfaction of self-interest. Or, “living as one likes”. The older view, echoing Aristotle, holds that “Liberty is the cultivated ability to exercise self-governance, to limit ourselves in accordance with our nature and the natural world”. In other words, making yourself free from your base desires, or doing the opposite of “living as one likes”.
Another way of describing the new freedom, or “rights”, is the abdication of all duties and responsibilities. True liberation from all non-chosen relationships. This implies a state of nature in which human beings are perfectly equal and perfectly free and don't take on any obligations or responsibilities, except the ones they consent to. The goal is for our personal obligations to be minimized to the point where all interactions can either be handled by the market or the state.
Of course, the consent model shrivels immediately upon inspection. After all, we are born into families and are families are born within countries, none of which we’ve consented to. From the very beginning, we are dependent on a society we are part of a civilization that we were born into and could never escape. The “social contract” is a myth.
The Rousseauian way of looking at it is, “I didn’t consent to this. Everything must change: The Culture. The State. Human Nature.” A better way of looking at it is, this “I’m a part of something bigger than me. A gift I’ve inherited from the past”. Obviously among interpersonal relationships, consent is very important, but when it comes to the family or culture or country you’re born into, you can’t expect to consent to that.
The pre-liberal tradition had rights, but they corresponded with duties, whether they be your duties as a parent or a citizen.
The new view of freedom is based on John Stuart Mill’s harm principle, the belief that an individual’s choices may never be legitimately hampered, by anyone at all, except if he is harming others.
We previously understood that an excess of freedom made it hard to avoid the things that lead to a bad life: Gambling, porn, drug-abuse etc. Today, we admit that those things cause harm, but we see giving people the freedom to succumb to sin and deprivation as a basic human right, as granting them dignity. This is why we’d rather give homeless people drugs than send them to rehab or even strongly suggest it.
Overtime, of course, the harm principle would get abused in other ways, where harm expanded to mean something as innocuous as speech someone doesn’t like, and that the people who had less privileges were the only ones who could define “harm”.
So the harm principle, which was originally meant to sort of reduce the ability of a government or authority to go after our experience of pleasure, now became used as a weapon to go after people who did not submit to compelled speech.
So in order to enforce freedom, paradoxically, one of the main roles of the liberal state becomes the active liberation of individuals from any existing limiting conditions, whether those be economic, familial, community-based, class-based, group-based, or even biologically based.
We must deploy the coercive power of government to promote freedom; we must limit freedom for the sake of freedom.
So under a consent based morality, any choice must be validated or else it is oppression. Which means every interaction is at risk of becoming oppression. Because if you need everyone to validate you at all times, and any violation of that that is a form of oppression, well then eventually you're going to avoid everyone lest any of them contradict what you believe about yourself at that given time.
This explains why some are trying to liberate consciousness from our own bodies, to fight back against what has not been chosen.
Indeed: A certain strain of liberal ideology, as well as redesigning culture, is also trying to redesign nature.
As R.R. Reno once put it: “If no man’s destiny is fixed at birth, why, ultimately, should any aspect of any person be fixed or limited? If there is no metaphysical content to nature, why cannot nature simply be overruled in any given case? What is nature but a set of irrational, or non-rational, restrictions?”
This definition of freedom as lack of constraint is almost the polar opposite of the classical and traditional Christian conceptions of liberty, which did not mean being free to do whatever one wished in the pursuit of pleasure, but being free from enslavement to one’s base appetites — a condition predicated on the cultivation of a self-discipline, through which one could, through the fulfillment of duties and obligations, achieve over the course of one’s life a lasting sense of meaning and happiness.
We are free now, freer than ever, and yet it’s not enough. Everywhere I look, I see people who are free — free to be alone and adrift, without callings or commitments.
Rousseau is the patron saint (and Patient Zero) of Leftism because he best embodied and exemplified both the Left conception of morality and the Left's belief in their divine right to rule.
First, as the post states, comes the Rousseauian conception of freedom, which his biography also underscores: not just all the babies he left on other doorsteps for other people to raise, but the way he treated his many hosts and benefactors. One wrong word, one insult to his vast amour-propre, and the generous friend became a hated foe to be denounced in public in perpetuity. Didn't they understand that they were blessed to be giving food and housing to a great genius? Didn't they understand that his whims were decrees, while the rest of us were put on earth to clean up after him? This, obviously, is the freedom (and morality) of the entitled teenager, who recognizes nothing larger than his own appetites.
Then, just like our modern American Leftists, what did Rousseau present as his credential to undertake vast social engineering? He had never led any men or any organization, had never built anything or served in any way anywhere. His claim to being an infallible philosopher-king rested on 1) all the books he'd read; and 2) his pure and beautiful heart. He knew deep in his heart that he was the most kind and loving creature who ever lived, and if we all just followed the commands of his heart, we'd eventually arrive back in Eden. He was too smart, too kind, too filled with love to ever be wrong about anything, or to ever have to worry that his utopian schemes might backfire.
"I have unlimited rights but zero responsibilities, my infallible feelings are superior (and impervious) to any and all facts, anyone who prevents me from getting my way is an evil tyrant." Sound familiar?
Rousseau may have been the first SJW.
I'd be very curious to know where exactly in the work of Locke and Mill they explicitly define liberty as freedom from any and all duties, responsibilities, limitations, etc. I'll grant that the definition you give may be what "liberty" and "liberalism" actually means nowadays, but just because an ideology can be taken to a logical extreme with serious negative consequences doesn't make the ideology itself intellectually suspect or morally bankrupt.
You write: "Of course, the consent model shrivels immediately upon inspection. After all, we are born into families and are families are born within countries, none of which we’ve consented to. From the very beginning, we are dependent on a society we are part of a civilization that we were born into and could never escape. The “social contract” is a myth."
No, we certainly can't change our DNA or deny that biological immutability exists (despite what trans rights activists will have you believe), but if I were to come from a family that's genuinely abusive and psychologically damaging, not only *could* I decide to disavow my family and build a "found family" of my choosing, it would be hard to argue the right thing to do would be anything else but. And while I'll never not be from the U.S., if I didn't like identifying as an American and wanted to be something else, there's nothing stopping me from moving to another country and taking on their identity (well, except for those pesky immigration laws, of course). True, my new family and/or nation wouldn't be my "real" family/nation in a very important sense, but if my choices of family/nation are actually beneficial for me (and not merely "living as I like"), I don't see why that distinction would be important.
Again, I can see how this line of thinking can lead to situations where one disavows their family and/or nation for inconsequential or specious reasons, and we've seen what dangers that leads to. Still, I'm not convinced that one must feel a sense of duty and loyalty to the family/nation/culture/society you were born into just because you were born into it.
Two more (very general) thoughts:
1) When I read critiques of liberalism like yours, I never get the sense that the people who make them ask themselves why liberalism - and its new definition of freedom (assuming that's how people like Locke and Mill would define freedom, that is) - emerged in the first place. Did Enlightenment liberalism come about because of a sudden paroxysm in the West of egotism and entitlement? Or was it in response to actual injustices, oppression, and evil being justified and held up by notions of tradition, customs, religion, etc.?
A while back I saw someone say that tradition is the solution to social problems that have been long since forgotten about, and when the tradition is removed the problems return. It's important to remember, though, that the opposite is true - traditions (whether they're rituals, mores, institutions, etc.) are usually done away with for very valid reasons, and just because those reasons may not exist in today's world doesn't mean we can assume they won't make a comeback if the traditions are reinstated.
2) This piece seems to imply that many aspects of "wokeness" - harm reduction, restrictions on free speech, expecting one's biases and misperceptions to be completely validated, thinking people can change their sex, etc. - are the natural outgrowth of liberalism, especially liberal conceptions of freedom. However, this line of thinking fails to account for how wokeness is a response to - and antithesis of - liberalism. Many people far more articulate than me have shown how wokeness bears more than a striking resemblance to Christian notions of original sin, faith, purification, eschatology, etc., and still others have talked about how this ideology judges individuals on their membership to various groups instead of their own words, deeds, and character. I think critics of liberalism fail to realize that the kind of societies they wish to create as an alternative will end up looking a lot more like wokeness than whatever idealized version of the past they hold.